Skip to main content

Confrontational scavenging as a possible source for language and cooperation

Abstract

The emergence of language and the high degree of cooperation found among humans seems to require more than a straightforward enhancement of primate traits. Some triggering episode unique to human ancestors was likely necessary. Here it is argued that confrontational scavenging was such an episode. Arguments for and against an established confrontational scavenging niche are discussed, as well as the probable effects of such a niche on language and co-operation. Finally, several possible directions for future research are suggested.

Introduction

Language and cooperation form perhaps the most distinctive features of the human species. That language is unique to humans is almost universally acknowledged, even by those on opposite sides of the nativist/empiricist debate [1, 2]. While closest relatives of humans have been shown to have a capacity, under intensive training, for rudimentary forms of language [3], there is no indication that this capacity would ever have developed in the wild. Cooperation on the scale practised by humans is found elsewhere only among the hymenoptera, although there the basis (kin selection) is quite different from that of human cooperation [4]. It would be remarkable enough if any species, in the 4-7 my (million-year) time-span suggested for human evolution, had developed just one of these traits. That each developed independently in the same species, with its own separate evolutionary history, seems unlikely.

Could co-operation have led to language, or vice versa? There are problems with either solution. A "language-first" model faces the difficulty that language presupposes a level of trust unlikely to exist given the conniving and deceit found among nonhuman primates [5]. Why would anyone believe verbal utterances, given that words are such "cheap signals" [6], and how, if no-one believed them, could language have taken root? However, a "cooperation-first" model faces an equal difficulty in that most evolutionary studies of human cooperation assume the existence of communal norms and the punishment of infractors [79]. It remains unclear how such norms could have been established without any kind of language.

The issues are further complicated by the fact that neither the evolution of language nor the evolution of co-operations is as yet well understood. There is still no consensus as to how language originated [10, 11], while even recent work on the origins of co-operation. (typically treated as some mix of inclusive fitness, reciprocal altruism and group selection with other factors) [12, 13] fails to offer an entirely convincing account of the differences in both degree and kind of cooperation that distinguish humans from apes. Most accounts of both language and cooperation invoke enhancement of, and interaction between, factors at least rudimentarily present in other species, even though, as niche construction theory [14] has recently emphasized, novel and unique traits from beaver dams to bat echolocation have typically originated through adaptation to some new and highly specific niche.

This is not to diminish the vital roles played by these pre-existing factors and the equally important roles they would play once language and cooperation had begun to develop. Clearly, such factors form necessary prerequisites for both language and cooperation, but were they sufficient? If they were, it remains a mystery why language and cooperation are hyper-developed in one species, while in the most closely related species they are either completely absent (language) or remain minimal (cooperation). The emergence of unique novel behaviours would appear to necessitate some equally unique triggering mechanism, such as entering a new niche that demanded such behaviours if the problems that niche presented were to be solved. In this paper we evaluate and strengthen the suggestion [15] that the confrontational scavenging scenario can resolve the issues.

The case for a confrontational scavenging niche

Evidence exists that just such a niche may have been occupied by human ancestors starting around 2 mya and lasting perhaps several hundred thousand years. That niche was confrontational scavenging, sometimes called "power scavenging" [16]. However, no-one has yet claimed confrontational scavenging as a fully developed niche, and some have even denied that it could be one (see Section 3 below). Accordingly, before discussing possible consequences for human behaviour of a confrontational scavenging niche, the case for the existence of such a niche must be established. Although much of the evidence is of necessity indirect and inferential, it shows substantial convergence from diverse areas, including ecological opportunity, technology, sequences of bone markings, optimal foraging theory, and behavioural and physiological changes affecting Homo around 2 mya.

Ecological opportunity

In the late Pliocene the East African climate became considerably drier and more variable, giving rise to large areas of savannah and many new species including herbivorous megafauna [17]. Carcasses of such megafauna offered immense quantities of meat. However, that meat could not be accessed immediately, because the toughness of megafauna hides made them impossible for mammalian teeth to breach until build-up of interior gases split them [18]. This left a window of at least several hours that could be exploited by any species capable of penetrating hides. Note that while megafauna carcasses were increasing in number, climate change was sharply reducing the staple primate diet of fruit and nuts.

Did such carcasses represent "rare bonanzas", as some sources have suggested [19], or were they common enough to have offered a (relatively) regular food source? There are no reliable estimates of prehistoric megafauna populations, so the best we can do is extrapolate from existing populations. Recent studies of elephant populations in two national parks [20, 21] agree on a density of 0.3 per km2, but both sources note that in earlier decades populations were close to 1.0 per km2. For sustainable population density in a terrain similar to that of the climax-savannah period, an even higher density has been suggested [22]. Since elephants live on average 70 years, an area of 1,000 square kilometres--not an unreasonable annual range for Homo erectus--should yield on average a dead elephant at least every month. Moreover, elephant ancestors would have been far from the only megafauna available.

Technology

Both the Oldowan and Acheulean industries provided flakes as a by-product of hand-axe and hammer-stone manufacture. It has been experimentally demonstrated that flake tools will quite easily cut through the hides of elephants, while Acheulean hand-axes are well adapted for subsequent butchery [18].

Hand-axes could have had a dual function in confrontational scavenging, since the latter would inevitably involve hostile interactions with competing scavengers (including predators larger and fiercer than their modern equivalents). Hand-axes have aerodynamic properties that would have made them useful projectiles [23]; scepticism about their effectiveness [24] relates to hunting rather than scavenging, where deterrence rather than killing or capture would be the goal. With flakes and hand-axes at their disposal, hominins had all the tools they needed to practice effective confrontational scavenging.

Sequence of bone markings

The sequence of tool- and tooth-marks on bones can be read to infer priority of access to a carcass. If cut marks are superimposed on tooth marks (as is mostly the case before 2 mya) the carcass has been accessed by hominins only after other species have accessed it. If, however, tooth-marks are superimposed on cut-marks, human ancestors must have been the first to access the carcass. Priority of access could, of course, have resulted from either confrontational scavenging or hunting. However, hunting large animals requires adequate weapons, and there is no indication that contemporary hominins possessed these. A number of sources [19, 2527] indicate that subsequent to 2 mya this second sequence of bone markings occurred with increasing frequency. This could happen only if the hominins involved had been consistently accessing carcasses before other scavengers.

Optimal foraging theory

Optimal foraging theory [28] proposes that a species will choose, out of available foods, those yielding the highest calorific gain relative to energy expended in obtaining them. Meat from megafauna carcasses offered the highest calorific yield available for any savannah-dwelling species (bone-marrow might be richer ounce for ounce, but quantities were far smaller). Engaging in confrontational scavenging does not preclude bone-marrow extraction; both might have been practised. However, since Oldowan technology is adequate for marrow-extraction but much less suited to confrontational scavenging than Acheulian technology, one plausible scenario would be a speciation event in which a hand-axe-wielding erectus split off from a bone-cracking habilis. Once located, exploiting a megafauna carcass took little time and energy relative to the nutritional yield. While confrontational scavenging was more dangerous than other foraging methods, risks could be reduced by numbers of participants and aimed throwing.

Behavioural and physiological changes

The evolution of human scavenging falls into two phases: catchment scavenging and territory scavenging [29]. Catchment scavenging involved working within a restricted area where natural resources were plentiful, while territory scavenging involved ranging over much wider areas with relatively little attention paid to resource richness. The shift in strategies occurred, again, around 2 mya, and is consistent with a change from passive scavenging of mainly bones and discarded meat scraps to confrontational scavenging of entire carcasses, the location and timing of which were unpredictable. It is not necessary to claim that hominins became obligate confrontational scavengers (few if any animals are), only that confrontational scavenging was added to the arsenal of hominin behaviours as the currently most favoured strategy.

Given the 2 mya boundary between catchment and territory scavenging, we may (very roughly) associate the former with Homo habilis and the latter with Homo erectus. The two species show considerable physiological differences [30, 31]: erectus was larger and taller than habilis, with a more rangy build, legs better adapted for rapidly covering long differences, and a considerably greater brain size. Were these changes adaptations for endurance hunting [32] or scavenging [33]? Since endurance hunting would have separated one or a very few individuals from the rest of the group, exposing them to predation at a time before there were spears or arrows for self-defence, confrontational scavenging (which might have involved covering long distances, but in larger groups) seems a more plausible selective pressure for the suite of behavioral and physiological characteristics found in erectus.

Arguments against confrontational scavenging

Although, as shown above, a wide range of data is consistent with the confrontational scavenging hypothesis, a number of scholars have suggested that the practice cannot have played any significant role in human development. For instance, Dusseldorp [34] argues that "Since scavenging is a competitive niche requiring specialization, it was considered unlikely that hominins ever relied on this strategy." However, niche construction theory has shown that specialization does not precede exploitation of a niche--rather, new-niche occupation by initially unspecialized species is precisely what drives specialization [14].

The fact that scavenging behaviour is rare or non-existent among other primates is often taken as evidence against scavenging by human ancestors [35]. However, this argument is based on the assumption that all human behaviour is grounded in ape behaviour, and that straight-line evolution from great apes is an indisputable fact. There seems little empirical evidence for such assumptions. Behaviour is determined at least as much by environmental and ecological considerations as by genetic factors; consider for instance the fact that the hyrax, the elephant and the manatee are more closely related to one another than they are to other species [36]. If human ancestors found that scavenging was necessary for subsistence, it is unlikely that great-ape genes would have deterred them.

The belief that megafauna carcass finds were rare events, discussed in Section 2.1 above, seems to rest on the assumption that our ancestors would have been limited to carcasses that, to their surprise perhaps, they happened to stumble upon. It is much likelier that organisms whose brain sizes often fell within the human range would have taken a proactive approach, perhaps even tracking and following herds as was done by humans in the Upper Paleolithic. While the returns of such a strategy might not always have sufficed for subsistence, temporary reversion to gathering, bone scavenging and opportunistic hunting was always a possibility.

Finally, Geist [35] asks, "If scavenging was important, how did it lead to the adaptations characteristic of Homo?" The remainder of this paper seeks to answer this precise question, giving substance to the caveat that ends an earlier sentence by the same author: "Scavenging is not part of a sufficient explanation of human adaptations--at least not yet" (emphasis added).

Why confrontational scavenging required atypical primate behaviours

To access megafauna carcasses in the face of severe competition required that human ancestors communicate in ways no other primate had done, and cooperate to a degree unknown among other primates.

There are no reliable estimates for human band size circa 2 mya. Due to the sparseness of food supplies under savanna conditions, as well as other factors that limit band size even in modern foraging populations [37], it seems likeliest that bands of < 40 individuals would have followed the common primate behaviour of fission-fusion foraging, dividing into smaller groups (but not too small to protect against predation) by day to cover the maximum area, and meeting in refugia at night. To simultaneously butcher a carcass and drive off competitive scavengers required more numbers than such smaller groups could provide, necessitating the active co-operation of a large majority in each band.

To recruit adequate numbers, two critical acts had to be performed. The carcass finders had to communicate information that lay far outside the sensory range of potential recruits, and they had to convince those recruits to abandon whatever they were doing and travel to a perhaps quite distant site for an invisible goal.

The communication problem

The vast majority of animal communication systems, including all other primate systems, are unable to give information about anything that falls outside the potential sensory range of recipients. Exceptions are the systems of eusocial species (ants [38], bees [39]...) that share a feature otherwise unique to human language, displacement, making it possible to refer to events remote in space and/or time. It is noteworthy that ants and bees also regularly forage food sources (pollen in the case of bees, larger dead organisms in the case of ants) that are too large and/or too transient for one or a few individuals to fully exploit; these are precisely the circumstances that require recruitment. The location of such sources, which may lie some distance (in the case of bees, miles) away, is signalled by stereotyped dances (bees) or chemical or behavioural [40] means (ants). In other words, animals are limited only by their phenotypes in the means of signalling they adopt.

Band members who had located a carcass would have had to use sounds, gestures or mimicry to inform potential recruits of what they had found. The modality, as the hymenopteran examples suggest, is unimportant--whatever worked would have been chosen, what mattered was displacement itself. Reference to absent entities is the first step towards symbolism, the capacity that underlies all of human cognition including language [41]. While it is true that in ants and bees, displacement never moved further towards true symbolism, its consequences would have been far more widespread in a species with 4 × 104 more brain cells and a large suite of prerequisites for language.

The cooperation problem

It is one thing to convey information--quite another to get other individuals to act on that information.

Primates are not known for their cooperativeness. To the contrary, they are highly competitive and willing to deceive one another in pursuit of individual goals [5]. They cooperate only to the extent that this furthers the latter, and only on the basis of things immediately apparent to them. This type of behaviour has been called "competitive cooperation", as opposed to "collaborative cooperation" where "the resource is not manifest, but mainly imagined" [42] (the latter being typical of human cooperation).

Thus, even assuming that communication was successful (i.e. recipients realized that a megafauna carcass was available at location X), it does not follow that recipients would automatically co-operate. Those who did not go for the carcass would suffer a penalty in terms of less food (unless dependent and needy); for such punishment only memory and individual recognition were needed. Boyd et al. considered the origin of coordinated punishment. The authors observe that "A complete account of the evolution of cooperation must explain how punishing strategies can increase when rare." [[43], p. 620]. Here they wouldn't have been rare even at the beginning. Imagine a situation in which three out of four subgroups of the band co-operate but the fourth doesn't. As a direct result, scavengers drive the band from the carcass, and three-fourths of the band go hungry. It does not stretch the imagination to ponder the consequences of such defection. The key point in the scenario is that all members of the group must cooperate simultaneously if a goal advantageous to all is to be achieved. Individuals who nonetheless wish to avoid physical danger during the action would be immediately noted and punished in a coordinated way by the same group that had already cooperated in the scavenging. These considerations do not exclude the possibility that reputation-based punishment may have later contributed to the extension of cooperation [44, 45], but we also note that the cited models concern pairwise interactions only. Some of the tools used in scavenging may have been used as projectiles for coordinated punishment [46] of defectors after the event, but we feel that such use at the stage discussed may have been rather casual.

One way to determine the probabilities here would be to look at temporal profiles of contemporary megafauna carcass sites. Surprisingly there seems to be little if any literature on this topic. Available evidence comes mainly from wild-life photographers, and suggests considerable variability at such sites. In one account, a hippopotamus was being consumed by nineteen lions, although how long the carcass had been available is not known [47]. In another, however, an elephant that "must have died within the last day or two" was found to be "surprisingly intact", and attended only by a few jackals and a number of vultures [48]; it was only some days later that lions appeared.

Empirically it is known that in the case of cooperative hunting not everybody cooperates (there is always a fraction of laggards), but even more interesting, it seem that in lions [49] and at least in some hunter-gatherer groups [50, 51] such laggards are not punished. Two remarks are in order. First, we do not know whether this finding generalizes to all hunter-gatherers, even less whether it applied to ancient scavengers. Second, as we shall see shortly, in similar games there can be stable coexistence of cooperators and defectors even without punishment.

Supporting models

Though an adequate model involving all important features (communication, cooperative scavenging, group competition and punishment) does not exist in the literature, we call attention to the fact that non-linear N-person public good games (reviewed in [52]) offer very encouraging results already in the right direction. In these models cooperators pay a cost and contribute to a public good that, in the simplest case, can be consumed by all members. Cooperators pay a fixed per capita cost and benefits are shared. Non-linearity means that fitness increases non-linearly with the frequency of cooperators. For the scavenging scenario the "teamwork dilemma" [53] is the most relevant where it holds that out of a group of N players at least k must cooperate to produce the public good, thus k is the threshold value. A general outcome of these games is that unless the costs are prohibitively high, there is the possibility of locally stable coexistence even in a well-mixed population with random assortment into potentially cooperating groups [52]. Remarkably, the sharp threshold can be replaced practically with any sigmoid benefit function (increasing and diminishing returns for low and high numbers of actual cooperators, respectively). Punishment is not necessary for the existence of the cooperative equilibrium.

Boza and Számadó have developed these models further in order to elucidate the effects of multilevel selection (with or without local population structure) [54]. It was assumed that during group competition a group with a higher average payoff replaces a randomly chosen group with lower average fitness. Interestingly, they found that group selection does not lead to the fixation of the cooperative form either, but it brings the frequency of cooperators closer to the optimum number for the group (intuitively, if k cooperators are sufficient for the teamwork, the involvement of more agents is wasteful). Local spatial structure promotes cooperation in the model as it maintains a high level of cooperation even with high costs for both hunting and defence. It is even possible for cooperators to invade when rare, despite the positive costs to cooperation.

Consequences for language and cooperation

Of course the processes described above, even if successfully completed, could not, in and of themselves, have led to anything remotely approaching the levels of language or cooperation that characterize modern humans. What they could do, in a species with at least the cognitive capacities of a great ape, was kick-start two autocatalytic processes that could then join in a co-evolutionary spiral leading eventually to modern humans.

With regard to the first, communication, all that confrontational scavenging made available was an enhanced system of communication--a typical animal communication system (ACS) plus displacement. But displacement would have served as the wedge that broke the walls of the here-and-now that circumscribe almost all ACSs (including all ACSs of other neurologically-complex organisms), potentially allowing free reference to anything in the world, past or future, real or imagined. While at first this enhanced ACS might have been used solely for foraging, its utility in other spheres--pedagogy, planning, manipulation of others, and much more--would surely have become apparent, allowing its uses to extend, and its resources to become richer, as fast as the neurobiological changes necessary for full language could develop.

With regard to the second, cooperation, successful execution of confrontational scavenging would have immediately yielded tangible proof (in terms of a steady supply of high-quality nutriments) of the benefits of cooperation. Once it had been established, in one sphere at least, that cooperative strategies yielded better results than competitive strategies, such strategies would surely have spread to other domains. Increases in ways of cooperating would then have selected for genes that either favoured cooperation or suppressed overly competitive behaviours.

As Szathmáry and Számadó remark: "The evolution of language probably occurred in concert with the evolution of many of the other traits we associate with being human, such as the ability to fashion tools or a strong propensity to learn. If this is true, it suggests that we shouldn't be trying to understand one characteristically human trait in isolation from the others." [55]. Consonant with this view, the notion of a 'human-specific adaptive suite' entails a number of synergistic traits, including eminently language and cooperation, where selection on one would have accelerated the evolution of others [56]. The more cooperation, the more language was needed to practice it; the more language, the more avenues for cooperation opened up. All the factors previously invoked as directly selective of language and/or cooperation, from theory of mind to group selection, would have come into play. But as suggested in Section 1, language and cooperation on a human scale are so far from primate norms that the mere presence of potential preadaptations could not alone have precipitated them. They required a trigger of some kind, one unique to immediate human ancestors, and so far as is presently known confrontational scavenging was the only activity practiced by those ancestors that contained all the necessary components for such a trigger.

An analysis of the selective scenarios for language [57] concluded that none of them could account for all the criteria established for evaluation: honesty, groundedness, power of generalization and uniqueness. It strikes us that the cooperative scavenging scenario, for the first time in the literature, meets all these criteria.

Future research

The foregoing should serve as a prima facie case for regarding confrontational scavenging as a well-defined niche and possibly crucial in the emergence of human cooperation and language. However, much needs to be done in several areas of research before more definite conclusions can be reached.

Perhaps the most fundamental issue concerns how species with novel traits originate. The vast majority of explanations for how language and cooperation arose (a) fail to make specific reference to any detailed account of human evolution and (b) adopt multifactorial explanations of a kind seldom if ever invoked when other species are discussed [713]. More fine-grained studies of speciation are needed to determine what kinds of selective pressure cause such events.

A better understanding of the ecology of 2 mya, and how human ancestors fitted into it, is also required. Many parts of the jigsaw are to be found in this area. We need at least a rough estimate of population figures for a wide variety of species and we need a better understanding of hominin foraging patterns, including daily and annual ranges and band size. A vexing problem lies in the fact that territory scavenging entails deposits of bones that are widely and thinly scattered, making it difficult to determine the full scope of the role confrontational scavenging played in overall foraging patterns.

The suggested use of hand-axes as projectiles in the deterrence of rival scavengers should also be tested to resolve as far as possible disagreements over the functionality of this procedure. Careful statistical studies of microwear patterns and spatial distribution of hand-axes would help us determine their function(s).

Among the most potentially revealing of the studies suggested by the confrontational-scavenging hypothesis would be those involving species that faced a similar ecological problem: the need to practice recruitment in order to exploit large, unpredictable and transient food sources, with or without the complication of competition. Surprisingly few species seem to be faced with this problem; apart from bees and ants, the only case reported so far involves ravens [58]. Juvenile ravens are driven away from carcasses (in winter, almost the only form of nutrition) by mature mated pairs, but (apparently by exchanging information in nightly roosts) the former often manage to recruit sufficient numbers to drive the latter off. Here one finds competition within rather than between species, but the principles involved are the same. Whether ravens have indeed mastered displacement, and if so how they accomplish it, is currently under investigation [59].

There may, of course, be other species that face similar problems. Such species too would need to be studied from a comparative perspective. Even the existence of the few we know raises fascinating questions concerning the extent to which, given details of any ecological problem, we can predict how a species will solve it, and whether successful solutions are repeated regardless of phylogenetic distance between the species concerned. And even if the confrontational scavenging hypothesis fails to find support, the research it suggests should shed much light on both the history of our species and evolutionary processes in general. The aim is, as with other major transitions in evolution [60], to put forward a scenario about which we can all agree that this is how it could have happened, without necessarily ever being able to say that this was exactly how it did happen.

Our account is a logical analysis of a promising scenario. The phenomena we consider are dynamically complex, and in the absence of direct experimentation, strongly call for a modelling approach. In the next paper we demonstrate how communication and cooperation can together triumph in a population model (Szathmáry and Bickerton, forthcoming).

References

  1. Hauser M, Chomsky N, Fitch WT: The language faculty: who has it, what is it, and how did it evolve?. Science. 2002, 298: 1569-1579. 10.1126/science.298.5598.1569.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  2. Tomasello M: On the different origins of symbols and grammar. Language Evolution. Edited by: Christiansen MH, Kirby S. 2003, Oxford, Oxford Univ. Press, 94-110.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  3. Savage-Rumbaugh S, Rumbaugh D: The emergence of language. Tools, Language and Cognition in Human Evolution. Edited by: Gibson K, Ingold T. 1993, Cambridge, Cambridge Univ. Press, 86-108.

    Google Scholar 

  4. Foster KR, Ratnieks FLW: A new social vertebrate. Trends Ecol Evol. 2005, 20: 363-364. 10.1016/j.tree.2005.05.005.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  5. Whiten A, Byrne RA: Tactical deception in primates. Behav Brain Sciences. 1988, 11: 233-244. 10.1017/S0140525X00049682.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  6. Zahavi A: The fallacy of conventional signaling. Phil Trans R Soc London B. 1993, 340: 227-230. 10.1098/rstb.1993.0061.

    Article  CAS  Google Scholar 

  7. Henrich J, Boyd R: Why people punish defectors. J Theor Biol. 2001, 208: 79-89. 10.1006/jtbi.2000.2202.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  8. Fehr E, Fischbacher U, Gächter S: Strong reciprocity, human cooperation and the enforcement of social norms. Hum Nat. 2002, 13: 1-25. 10.1007/s12110-002-1012-7.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  9. Bowles S, Gintis H: The origins of human cooperation. Genetic and Cultural Evolution of Cooperation. Edited by: Hammerstein P. 2003, Cambridge MA, MIT Press, 429-444.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Christiansen MH, Kirby S, Eds: Language Evolution. 2003, Oxford, Oxford Univ. Press

    Google Scholar 

  11. Larson RK, Déprez V, Yamakido H, Eds: The Evolution of Human Language. 2010, Cambridge, Cambridge Univ. Press

    Google Scholar 

  12. Henrich J, Henrich N: Culture, evolution, and the puzzle of human cooperation. Cog Syst Res. 2006, 7: 220-245. 10.1016/j.cogsys.2005.11.010.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  13. Melis AP, Semmann D: How is human cooperation different?. Phil Trans R Soc B. 2010, 365: 2663-2674. 10.1098/rstb.2010.0157.

    Article  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  14. Odling-Smee FJ, Laland KN, Feldman MW: Niche Construction: The neglected process in evolution. 2003, Princeton, Princeton Univ. Press

    Google Scholar 

  15. Bickerton D: Adam's Tongue: How Humans Made Language, How Language Made Humans. 2009, New York, Hill and Wang

    Google Scholar 

  16. Bunn HT: Hunting, power scavenging, and butchering by Hadza foragers and by Plio-Pleistocene Homo. Meat-eating and Human Evolution. Edited by: Stanford CB, Bunn HT. 2001, Oxford, Oxford Univ. Press, 199-218.

    Google Scholar 

  17. de Menocal PB: African climate change and faunal evolution during the Pliocene-Pleistocene. Earth Planetary Sci Letters. 2001, 220: 3-24.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  18. Schick K, Toth N: Making Silent Stones Speak. 1993, New York, Simon and Schuster

    Google Scholar 

  19. Blumenschine RA: Characteristics of an early hominid scavenging niche. Curr Anthr. 1987, 28: 383-407. 10.1086/203544.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  20. Mubalama L: Population and distribution of elephants (Loxodonta Africana africana) in the central sector of the Virunga National Park, Eastern DRC. Pachyderm. 2000, 28: 44-55.

    Google Scholar 

  21. Demeke Y, Bekele A: Study on the elephants of Mago National Park, Ethiopia. Pachyderm. 2000, 28: 34-43.

    Google Scholar 

  22. Armbruster P, Lande R: A population viability analysis for African elephant (Loxodonta africana): How big should reserves be?. Cons Biol. 1993, 7: 603-610.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  23. O'Brien E: What was the Acheulean hand ax?. Curr Anthr. 1981, 22: 76-79. 10.1086/202607.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  24. Whittaker JC, McCall G: Handaxe-hurling hominids: An unlikely story. Curr Anthr. 2001, 42: 566-572. 10.1086/322547.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  25. Blumenschine RA, Cavallo JA: Competition for carcases and early hominid behavioral ecology. J Hum Evol. 1994, 27: 197-213. 10.1006/jhev.1994.1042.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  26. Monahan CM: New zooarchaeological data from Bed II, Olduvai Gorge, Tanzania: implications for hominid behavior in the early Pleistocene. J Hum Evol. 1996, 32: 93-128.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  27. Dominguez-Rodrigo MT, Pickering TR: Cutmarked bones from Pliocene archaeological sites at Gona, Afar, Ethiopia: implications for the function of the world's oldest stone tools. J Hum Evol. 2005, 48: 109-121. 10.1016/j.jhevol.2004.09.004.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  28. Stephens DW, Krebs JR: Foraging Theory. 1986, Princeton, Princeton Univ. Press

    Google Scholar 

  29. Larick R, Ciochon R: The African emergence and early Asian dispersals of the genus Homo. Am Sci. 1996, 84: 538-551.

    Google Scholar 

  30. Fleagle JL: Primate Adaptation & Evolution. 1998, New York, Academic Press

    Google Scholar 

  31. Anton SC: Natural history of Homo erectus. Am J Phys Anthr. 2003, 122 (Supp 37): 126-170.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  32. Carrier DB, Kapoor AK: The energetic paradox of human running and hominid evolution. Curr Anthr. 1984, 25: 483-495. 10.1086/203165.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  33. Bramble DM, Lieberman DE: Endurance running and the evolution of Homo. Nature. 2004, 432: 345-352. 10.1038/nature03052.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  34. Dusseldorp GL: A View to a Kill: Investigating Middle Palaeolithic Subsistence Using an Optimal Foraging Perspective. 2009, Leiden, Sidestone Press

    Google Scholar 

  35. Geist V: Commentary on Blumenschine. Curr Anthr. 1987, 28: 396-397.

    Google Scholar 

  36. Stanhope MJ, Waddell VG: Molecular evidence for multiple origins of Insectivora and for a new order of endemic African insectivore mammals. Proc Natl Acad Sci USA. 1998, 95: 9967-9972. 10.1073/pnas.95.17.9967.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  37. Marlowe FW: Hunter-gatherers and human evolution. Evol Anthr. 2005, 14: 54-67. 10.1002/evan.20046.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  38. Wilson EO: Chemical communication in the fire ant Solenopsis saevissima. Anim Behav. 1962, 10: 134-164. 10.1016/0003-3472(62)90141-0.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  39. von Frisch K: Honeybees: do they use direction and distance information provided by their dancers?. Science. 1967, 158: 1072-1076. 10.1126/science.158.3804.1072.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  40. Franks NR, Richardson T: Teaching in tandem-running ants. Nature. 2006, 439: 153-10.1038/439153a.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  41. Deacon T: The Symbolic Species. 1997, New York, Norton

    Google Scholar 

  42. Brink I, Gärdenfors P: Co-operation and Communication in Apes and Human. Mind & Language. 2003, 18: 484-501.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  43. Boyd R, Gintis H, Bowles S: Coordinated punishment of defectors sustains cooperation and can proliferate when rare. Science. 2010, 328: 617-620. 10.1126/science.1183665.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  44. Hilbe C, Sigmund K: Incentives and opportunism: from the carrot to the stick. Proc R Soc B. 2010, 277: 2427-2433. 10.1098/rspb.2010.0065.

    Article  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  45. Dos Santos M, Rankin DJ, Wedekind C: The evolution of punishment through cooperation. Proc R Soc B. 2011, 278: 371-377. 10.1098/rspb.2010.1275.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  46. Bingham P: Human evolution and human history: a complete theory. Evol Anthropol. 2000, 9: 248-257. 10.1002/1520-6505(2000)9:6<248::AID-EVAN1003>3.0.CO;2-X.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  47. Lions freed from hippo carcass. [http://www.earth-touch.com/result.php?i=Lions-feed-from-hippo-carcass]

  48. Dead elephant attracts scavengers. [http://www.earth-touch.com/result.php?i=Dead-elephant-attracts-scavengers]

  49. Heinsohn R, Packer C: Complex cooperative strategies in group-territorial African lions. Science. 1995, 269: 1260-1262. 10.1126/science.7652573.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  50. Marlowe FW: What explains Hadza food sharing?. Res Econ Anthr. 2004, 23: 69-88.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  51. Gurven M: To give and to give not: The behavioral ecology of human food transfers. Behav Brain Sci. 2004, 27: 543-583.

    Google Scholar 

  52. Archetti M, Scheuring I: Review: Cooperation in One-Shot Social Dilemmas without Assortment. J theor Biol accepted. 2011

    Google Scholar 

  53. Myatt DP, Wallace C: Evolution, teamwork and collective action: Production targets in the private provision of public goods. Econ J. 2009, 119: 61-90. 10.1111/j.1468-0297.2008.02206.x.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  54. Boza G, Számadó S: Beneficial laggards: multilevel selection, cooperative polymorphism and division of labour in Threshold Public Good Games. BMC Evol Biol. 2010, 10: 336-10.1186/1471-2148-10-336.

    Article  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  55. Szathmáry E, Számadó S: Language: A social history of words. Nature. 2008, 456: 40-41.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  56. Fedor A, Ittzés P, Szathmáry E: The biological background of syntax evolution. Biological Foundations and Origin of Syntax. Edited by: Bickerton D, Szathmáry E. 2009, Cambridge, MIT Press, 15-39.

    Google Scholar 

  57. Számadó S, Szathmáry E: Selective scenarios for the origin of natural language. Trends Ecol Evol. 2006, 21: 555-561. 10.1016/j.tree.2006.06.021.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  58. Heinrich B: Winter foraging at carcasses by three sympatric covids, with emphasis on recruitment by the raven, Corvus corax. Ecol Sociobiol J. 1988, 23: 141-156. 10.1007/BF00300349.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  59. Fitch WT, Huber L: Social cognition and the evolution of language: constructing cognitive phylogenies. Neuron. 2010, 65: 795-814. 10.1016/j.neuron.2010.03.011.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  60. Maynard Smith J, Szathmáry E: The Major Transitions in Evolution. 1995, Oxford, Freeman

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

Work by ES has been supported by the National Office for Research and Technology (NAP 2005/KCKHA005) and OTKA (National Scientific Research Fund, NK73047) in Hungary.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Eörs Szathmáry.

Additional information

Authors' contributions

DB conceived the paper, wrote the first draft. ES has contributed the discussion of models. Both authors read and approved the final manuscript.

Rights and permissions

This article is published under license to BioMed Central Ltd. This is an Open Access article distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution License (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/2.0), which permits unrestricted use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original work is properly cited.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Bickerton, D., Szathmáry, E. Confrontational scavenging as a possible source for language and cooperation. BMC Evol Biol 11, 261 (2011). https://0-doi-org.brum.beds.ac.uk/10.1186/1471-2148-11-261

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://0-doi-org.brum.beds.ac.uk/10.1186/1471-2148-11-261

Keywords